When I was working on my paper and researching the history and political turmoil that generated the massive human rights violations in Argentina, I was really fascinated to learn exactly how much the politics and the consummate ideologies of a society factor into the establishment of a regime that is capable of rationalizing (if that is even possible) acts such as genocide or clandestine disappearances. I don’t mean to imply that a country's particular set of political beliefs can somehow cause violations of human rights to occur on a national scale, but rather, in cases like Argentina, extreme polarization in the political landscape can initiate a pattern of retributive political violence that can escalade to human rights violations.
This was the thing that drew me towards writing a paper on Argentina, as it was a conceptualization of violence that I had never before come across. Before taking this class, I liked to think that at the core of most extreme cases of human rights violations there would necessarily be a vehement dictator or general that was at the root of such evil (Hitler comes to mind). And the one solace in such a conceptualization is the fact that in many ways if this was the case, the horrors of such violence could be ultimately blamed on one 'bad egg'. However, in learning about the work done by the South African TRC and the Argentinean CONADEP, I now know that there are an alarming number of cases where a whole sector of society can be held accountable for the tragedies such as Apartheid and Disappearing. To me, the fact that whole groups of people can be implicated in the orchestration of such immense tragedies is something that is almost as troubling as the tragedies themselves.
With that being said, here is an interesting video on the Universal Declaration of Human Rights that I came across as I was procrastinating this past weekend. At least maybe with work such as this, the international community is taking steps in the right direction. I certainly hope so. Enjoy...
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=hTlrSYbCbHE
Wednesday, December 9, 2009
Universal Declaration of Human Rights
Sunday, December 6, 2009
The Justice in Democracy
First, I think that my initial support for the reconciliation rule stemmed from my knowledge of apartheid and the eventual formulation of the South African TRC. Since the roots of the horrible human rights abuses in this case grew out of a state-sanctioned form of racism, I felt as though finding the truth and formulating some sort of justice for the victims to grab on to required some form of reconciliation above all else. Furthermore, since the South African TRC bartered amnesty for truth in an effort to put the society there back together, I thought that the form of government was somehow less important so long as a truth commission was given adequate legal space in which to operate. I know that this is one objection we discussed when debating these two objectives of truth commissions, but after learning about the 'disappeared' in Argentina and reading an article called "Settling Accounts: The Duty to prosecute the Human Rights Violations of a Prior Regime," I realized how supremely important the formulation of a domestic democratic order is to the effectiveness of a truth commission.
http://www.jstor.org.relay.rhodes.edu:2048/stable/pdfplus/796903.pdf
Essentially, this is article discusses the role of international laws concerning human rights and how they should be applied to various violations once the transition to a democratic regime has been made. Most importantly however, this article made me think about how human rights violations such as those in South Africa or Argentina occur in the first place. In both these cases, a totalitarian regime was established, which enabled ‘enforcers’ to invade every aspect of society - including basic human rights. Viewed in this light, a shift to democracy seems to be the only method of truly ending such violations. For me, this was best realized when looking at the case of Argentina, where a select group of military juntas staged a coup and subsequently began the act of 'disappearing' all those who were suspected of holding any type of anti-government sentiments. So, unlike the racial foundations of the events in South Africa, that which occurred in Argentina recognized no social, economic or political predilections. Whereas the horrors of apartheid can be tracked by its legislative record of repression, the military coup in Argentina marked a transition into a clandestine state-run terror operation that the government didn’t even recognize the existence of. As Ernesto Sabato appropriately points out, a veil of vulnerability and fear was immediately cast across the entire country:
A feeling of complete vulnerability spread throughout Argentine society, coupled with the fear that anyone, however innocent, might become a victim of the never-ending witch-hunt. Some people reacted with alarm. Others tended, consciously or unconsciously, to justify the horror. ’There must be some reason for it,’ they would whisper, as though trying to propitiate awesome and inscrutable gods, regarding the children or parents of the disappeared as plague-bearers. Yet such feelings could never be wholehearted, as so many cases were known of people who had been sucked into that bottomless pit who were obviously not guilty of anything.
In this situation seems as though any form of recovery from such widespread fear would end in the establishment of a democracy that would completely prevent such total abuse of power from ever happening again. And since a totalitarian government is essentially the required context for gross violations of human rights, the restoration of democracy, and more importantly handing control back to the people seems to be the most readily achievable form of justice regardless of the extent of prosecution.
Thursday, December 3, 2009
Sunday, November 29, 2009
Justice separate from Morality?
Instead, I think of justice as a purely practical measure, taken to keep the community under control. We all live in a big system, so there has to be some measure to maintain the order...of the system. It seems like morality is too subjective, like it might create some sort of inherent problems with our system of justice if we base it entirely on morality. I'm not really sure. But I think there's something like this in my Hume notes? Either way, I think this can apply to both justice overall and truth commissions as well.
truth commission without democracy?
While it is perhaps true that the truth commissions that we've read about (most notably the TRC, Argentina, and Chile) are only thinkable in democracies, I am not ready to say that no truth commission would be possible in a non-democracy. It seems that in the TRC, where the people of South Africa played a very big part in its creation, and in Chile and Argentina, where the truth commissions were accepted and reparations were given to victims by the new regimes, very democratic ideals are in play. But what if truth commissions looked different? What if they looked more like the El Salvador commission, which was made up of all foreigners? The people of El Salvador wanted the commission, but admitted that there were not people in El Salvador that would be able to uphold a commission without outside help. What about a country like Saudi Arabia? A place where human rights violations have definitely taken place, but yet it is not in the process of a democratic transition. There are certainly truths to be told in places that perhaps are unwilling or unready to tell them. So does that mean that truth commissions are not possible there? Or rather, are truth commissions necessary, but just might need to be spearheaded by the international community, with the help of the willing locals?
On the other hand, would truth commissions lose some of their legitimacy if they were not always started from within? If it becomes possible for the international community to put truth commissions in place as they seem fit, it seems like it could run the risk of becoming just a system of passing judgment and one state pointing out what is wrong about another, and altogether ignoring state sovereignty.
Naming Names
Ubuntu
I was introduced to the story of the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission in a class I took last year, and one of the themes I remember discussing at length is that of ubuntu as it was discussed by Desmond Tutu in his book No Future Without Forgiveness (1999). We have not discussed ubuntu much, and only the Elizabeth Kiss essay mentioned the concept. However, I feel that it is a useful concept to understand when evaluating the impact of the TRC on South African society.
In the book, Tutu defined a person with ubuntu as “open and available to others, affirming of others, does not feel threatened that others are able and good, for he or she has a proper self-assurance that comes from knowing that he or she belongs in a greater whole and is diminished when others are humiliated or diminished, when others are tortured or oppressed.”
Ubuntu is not just a local ideology in South Africa; it is a pan-African ideology emphasizing both individual humaneness and the interconnectedness of humanity. Ubuntu is not a rigid set of moral codes but a collectively understood philosophy by which to live. Though it was endorsed and encouraged by Tutu, it is not a Christian or otherwise religiously-derived concept, which legitimates its promotion by the TRC for those who claim the committee was biased toward Judeo-Christian notions of forgiveness and reconciliation.
Public testimony, interactions between victims and perpetrators, and amnesty as opposed to judicial punishment are all tools for achieving ubuntu. By sharing testimony with the world, allowing people to confront (and, if desired, make amends with) those who had wronged them, and not isolating but instead reintegrating offenders into society, the TRC facilitated the perpetuation of the African ideal of peace, togetherness, and mutual respect. Instead of ostracizing members of the apartheid regime, they sought to rehabilitate them into society, because, according to ubuntu, everyone’s humanity suffers. Due to the nature of their crimes the perpetrators were less than human, and confessing was a step towards restoring their own, and therefore society’s, humanity.
Elizabeth Kiss endows the concept of restorative justice with three objectives: “(1) to affirm and restore the dignity of those whose human rights have been violated; (2) to hold perpetrators accountable, emphasizing the harm that they have done to individual human beings; and (3) to create social conditions in which human rights will be respected” (79). All of these aims are compatible with ubuntu. Considering that ubuntu is a commonly shared African ideology that transcends cultural and language barriers, restorative justice seems like a much more beneficial and favorable option than retributive justice for post-apartheid South Africa to pursue.
prescribed shame?
Since last weeks discussion I wanted to renew the subject of whether or not truth commissions should release names. Some said that they should because it would lead the community to shaming the criminals, thus punishing them even though they were given amnesty. The other people class noted that shaming was too grave of a punishment, and that names should be with held so that shaming would not take place. But, the problem is which is more just?
It seems that the purpose of truth commissions is in the name: Truth. The purpose of revealing the truth in these hearings is the hope that the community will, upon hearing these criminals tell and take responsibility for their actions, restore its relationship to the part of the community that is now the basically criminals. The idea is that the healthy part of the community comprising of the victims will, after hearing the testimony will have stared to overcome their personal grievances and begin to reaccept the perpetrators of the crimes against them into the victims community.
The issue is to some shaming. Some as mentioned above, say that if names are released that the victims will shame the criminals not only negating their amnesty, but also diving the community further. This would defeat the original purpose of the truth commission, if it were true. But, the fact of the matter is that feeling shame is part of human nature. We cannot prescribe shame any more than we can prescribe disappointment as a punishment of any sort. The problem is that you cannot cast shame, because the perpetrator who breaks line with his community’s norms only feels shame.
Shame is cultural, and not at all universal in nature. For example in America we were shoes all the time in our homes, however in Japan it is very impolite and rude to wear your shoes even in your own home. Now if I went to Japan and I wore my shoes into someone’s home without knowing that I was breaking social custom I would feel no shame, until I became accustomed to the social norm.
In This same way sociopaths, or any person that has been so damaged as to no longer recognize social norms, are incapable of feeling shame and in this way would not feel shame even if they were out of sync with their entire community. For this reason it is impossible to cast shame or even prescribe it as a punishment, even if to feel it is the norm. Also this eliminates any reason to withhold names from truth commissions, because there is no way to argue that shame is a predicted punishment.
The Necessity of Morality
Punishment by Shame or "Hard Time"
The first possible solution for me is shame through the perpetrator being made know to the public. Shame punishes an individual on many levels. On a large scale, the perpetrator is now known to have committed their crime by the public, and therefore will most likely experience humiliation for the rest of their life. They will have difficulty obtaining a job and may therefore develop anger with those who have bestowed this shame upon them. This stands in the way of a community being unified, which is important for a successful truth commission. Shame also affects the individual’s personal life. In the case of South Africa, individual’s families often had no idea the atrocities they were committing. Many families were devastated to hear the horrors, their spouse, parent, or even child being turned into a monster in their eyes. Of course, this most likely would occur had the individual been processed in a judicial system, so I am not sure it is how this can be avoided without amnesty being given to an individual with only the prosecutors and perpetrators knowing what happened.
My primary concern regarding shame as a form of punishment is that I do not believe that all human beings feel shame. Unfortunately, this can become a circular argument very quickly because of the diversity of views toward human nature. I believe that some individuals can become immune to shame through repeated exposure or involvement in the sort of horrors that the truth commissions address. I do not believe that an individual is born into this mentality or born “evil”, but one can become dulled to shame. So does this make shame an impossible punishment for certain individuals? And if so, how does one gauge who deserves an alternative punishment? One could certainly fake feelings of shame and remorse? If an individual has no desire to integrate into the community, and merely gives up the truth in public to receive amnesty, is justice served?
I believe that some form of correctional education is required for justice to truly be served. I do not see shame as a final solution to just punishment. While our current jail facilities are certainly no more effective (or possibly even as effective) than shame, a reformed system could be the solution. This would involve implementation of stronger educational programs within the penal system, more humane facilities and treatment of inmates, legal ramifications for prejudicial treatment of those who are reentering society, and many other changes that are far and beyond my knowledge. While I am tempted forget about the possibility of change and consider this road helpless, I cannot help but hear Dr. J scolding my laziness and ignorance.
Minow’s Remdey of Acknowledgment
Prosecutions are undeniably flawed. Legal battles and massive prosecutions can be messy, and ineffective. They may only perpetuate the “eye for an eye” mentality and they fail to answer the questions that many families have concerning their loved ones.
Minow maintains, “the aspiration to develop as full an account as possible requires a process of widening the lens, sifting varieties of evidentiary materials, and drafting syntheses of factual material that usually does not accompany a trial.” (239) Thus, an alternative is required to replace the unsatisfactory trial process.
Minow argues that individuals can publicize their experiences and pain. This process would allow the victim and the community to overcome the pain together. “Acknowledgement” of the crimes will ease the pain of those suffering and simultaneously develop the fullest account of the events.
I think Minow is onto something. The venting process would be similar to speaking to a psychiatrist. By simply talking to someone, victims can relieve some of the stress and pain. It provides relief (for the victim) and recognition (for the community). Public recognition, after all, is a crucial aspect of the truth commission.
The full recognition of political atrocities (by the victims and the community) will, ideally, restore the “dignity” of the harmed parties. Minow emphasizes and reemphasizes the need for victims to tell their stories so the community can gather information and begin to heal.
The process of healing that Minow advocates recognizes that prosecutions are all but impossible. Rather than suffering in silence behind closed doors, victims would be able to shift the focus to communal healing. Thus, themes of healing and progress take the place of anger and uncertainty.
Truth commissions, unlike prosecutions, “emphasize the experiences of those victimizes”, create a historical record of the events, and proactively begins the healing process. While the “restorative power of truth telling” is only a small step in overcoming atrocious crimes against humanity, it is an effective, proactive process that emphasizes healing rather than exacerbating rage. Restoring dignity and answering lingering questions is necessary. Considering this, perhaps truth commissions are more effective in healing and understanding these crimes.
TRC v CEH
An interesting point that another author makes is that most people in Guatemala knew who the perpetrators were, but were powerless to convict or confront them. The main sentiment in Guatemala was the recovery of loved ones who were “disappeared” or killed. Because of this, naming names was not as important as retrieving information. This was obviously not a sentiment shared with all Guatemalans, for the initial response to the fact that the CEH would not name names was fiercely negative. The anonymity of the report led people to believe that this truth commission would be little more than a watered-down, apologetic paper that would never have any effect on the country’s future. Many were glad to hear that once the report was published, it blamed the state for 93% of the human rights violations.
Another place a policy of anonymity can be effective is in a state that has a weak judicial system. It is not fair to hand over the burden of prosecuting each individual to the next government, and could possibly destabilize their already weak power. In the case of Guatemala, the judicial system in place before the peace agreements that ended the civil war was but a shadow of what it used to be. Even as late as 2001, Guatemala is still considered a “weak country” according to the UN.
I am not arguing that a policy of anonymity is always correct, but rather I am trying to demonstrate that the decision to release names should be considered on a case-to-case basis. I will argue that in a state of transitional justice, a policy of anonymity seems to be more effective because of the frailty of the new government and judicial system.
The Punitive Approach
Recently a Ukrainian-American man named John Demjanjuk was arraigned in Germany on 27,900 counts of being an acessory to murder, accused of serving as a camp guard at the Sobibor concentration camp during the Second World War. It may well be one of the last war-crimes trials for alleged perpetrators of the Holocaust (Demjanjuk is 89 and wheel-chair bound). As the victims and villians of that atrocity are fading into history, it is worth examining the merits of the approach that has been taken by Germany and the world community in dealing with the legacy of the crime against humanity par excellence (if such a term is appropriate), particularly as it contrasts with the route of the truth commisions in South Africa and elsewhere.
The reconciliatory approach of the South African TRC was justified in part by the claim (true enough) that traditional judicial procedures could never hope to properly identify and punish all those culpable for crimes commited under apartheid, and for this reason is sometimes directly compared to the Nurmemberg trials and other legal actions taken against German war criminals. Since far more individuals were involved in Nazi Germany's machinery of mass murder than have ever been prosecuted, the argument goes, Nuremberg and the other anti-Nazi tribunals are essenntially failures because they purported to satisfy the demands of justice for the Holocaust, something that they could not possibly accomplish. The amnesty-granting truth commision is converesely held to obtain a higher "restorative justice" by airing out all the details and constructing a new shared narrative for reconcilation which only it can provide.
Looking at Germany over six decades after the Holocaust, I am inclined to think that perhaps the traditonal judicial approach to atrocities has been given short shrift by the boosters of the TRC. The Nuremberg tribunals certainly did not mete out retribution to all those responsible for the Nazi regime's genocides, but it definitively established the unacceptability of the crimes of the accused and laid the groundwork for many more trials to come in the ensuing decades. Nobody would argue that all the responsible parties have been punished (just as nobody would pretend that every single crime of apartheid has properly come to light through the truth commision process), but many have. In terms of "restorative truth" it is hard to fault the shared social consensus that has developed in Germany (and the world) about the massacres: something that must be remembered and never repeated. Modern Germany is a land where such Jews as remain are accorded full rights (and no small degree of deference) and Holocaust denial is illegal. Germany has also taken a leading role in fighting against genocides beyond its borders (as in the Balkans).
Of course, the South African truth commision may well have been more suited for the particular needs of that nation (as I think it indeed was), but reasoning from the particular to the general may be misguided on this subject. If the creation of a democratic society that has drawn the proper lessons from its past is the goal of any effort to deal with a legacy of crimes against humanity (as is often stated of truth commisions), it seems that the traditional methods of dealing with individual culprits need not stand in the way.
Broadcasting.
On one hand it seems like a decent idea, and that victims could actually benefit from this. Having people show their support, and reiterate the fact that people sympathize with them must be a positive part of their progress towards healing. Furthermore, if other victims see these testimonies that are publicized, they may come forward with valuable information, not to mention it may help in their healing as well.
But on the other hand, it seems that this publicity could be detrimental. I feel that instead of helping the victims, it could possibly induce shame with them instead. While some people may be proud of what they had endured, and want to use their voices as a tool, others may be hurt by the constant reminder of their pain. Until a certain point in healing has been reached, it seems that this broadcasting may hold some victims back from healing at a desirable pace.
The problem with this however is that no one will heal at the same pace as another person, and because of such society cannot just halt all things that may get in the way of it. Even though both options – broadcasting the victims’ testimonies or refraining from such – can both cause psychological damage, one must be chosen. While it has damaging properties, I guess in the end I could see more benefits coming from broadcasting the testimonies, but I’m still not comfortable with it.
Mercy & Justice
In class last Friday, we talked about Kiss’ essay in which she believes that if restorative justice focuses too much on reconciliation and not punishment, it would transcend the dichotomy of punishment and reconciliation and introduce mercy into justice. We went on to say that mercy can suspend laws, but not justice as the empathy associated with mercy coincides with the idea of justice. Although it can be reasonably argued, I’m still having trouble with the fact that something so personal as mercy can be included in a process so public. Yes, shame is more expressed through actions than mercy is, but to me they both are private matters that should remain separate from the process of seeking justice.
A Fairly Digressive Argument for Naming Names
Saturday, November 28, 2009
"Moral Hatred"
The TRC offered amnesty to perpetrators in exchange for a comprehensive truth of the acts they committed. At times this included detailing the atrocities committed to the spouse, children, or friends of the deceased or disappeared. For many of the victims attaching a face to the perpetrator, could initiate the healing process, but for others it could provide a focal point for their anger. This “moral hatred” would only be compounded by the fact that the victim can no longer seek prosecution of the perpetrator because of the amnesty they received. Kiss noted that in order to accept restorative justice, one must accept the premise that an individual can be transformed after they’ve committed a crime. Even if this is something that happens, I find it difficult to believe that in all cases the perpetrator has a change of heart and truly feels remorse for their actions. This encapsulates many of the criticism that there were Christian undertones in the TRCs organization. If the path to restoring the society is through a change of heart in the perpetrator, can the commissioners truly prescribe that?
Kiss noted that the idea of healing from restorative justice only came about from deliberation by the commissioners when drafting their final report; moreover, a whole only 17% of the South African society believed the TRC promoted reconciliation. Ideally Truth Commissions seek to restore the relationship between the victim and perpetrator, but if the victim does not forgive or if the perpetrator does not feel remorse this is impossible. Moreover, neither of those events can be prescribed, they occur spontaneously. Perhaps the real restorative nature of a Truth Commission is between the victim and the society as well as the perpetrator and society. By providing the victim with a conduit for their suffering, they are able to reintegrate with other human beings who empathize with their condition. For the perpetrators, they receive amnesty but at a cost of shame, shame which ultimately could lead them to feel remorse and undergo a "change of heart." If the ultimate goal is to find the truth that led to a systemic authorization of crimes against humanity and prevent it from happening again, Truth Commissions may be able to find success.
Friday, November 20, 2009
naming names
For example, I think that without at least a functioning judicial system, and a basic respect for the rule of law that the judiciary is supposed to represent, that naming names would be a dangerous idea both for the victims and the perpetrators. Even if the courts are obviously and horribly biased, so much so that the population has no trust for the rule of law they represent, it is important that through the Commission a country's judicial system is able to regain respect and authority so that their own verdicts and administration of the law are not disregarded. Without this basic respect for rule of law, the prospects of violence erupting after naming names seems great. For example, in Mozambique there was so little countrywide respect for rule of law that if someone testified against another in their village they could expect their house to be killed or for their property to be destroyed. Similarly, the Burundi Commission of Inquiry had trouble even getting people to provide testimony at all since the courts and the Army were filled with people who were responsible for the mass killings that took place in 1993. Naming names, then, would have been suicidal for the victims of the conflict who wished to tell their stories.
On the other hand, naming names in a country lacking respect for the judiciary or without a program to protect the perpetrators of the crimes runs the danger of promoting vigilantism. In South Africa, the truth commission was able to support a witness protection program that protected those who testified against powerful political figures as well as those who admitted to carrying out crimes under the previous regimes. It seems unlikely that anyone would have come forward if testifying only left them open to be killed by an upset witness.
If neither witness protection or respect for rule of law exist then, it seems like naming names would be a very irresponsible way to treat both the victims and the perpetrators of the crimes in question. While it may be impossible to predict the consequences of a decision, the risk of choosing to name names for the sake of truth without first considering the potentially deadly outcomes is reckless. While the truth would be upheld, the cost of the truth in terms of the danger that naming names would put on witness and perpetrators alike in a insecure, lawless, situation, and the cost that the resulting violence would have on the prospects for a society's move towards a peaceful future, would not be worth the risk.
Monday, November 16, 2009
Nozick Revisted
But what are we to do with something so thorny as the institution of torture? To me, there is a humongous difference between parties agreeing to certain entitlements and people "consenting" to be tortured. Wasn't it Locke who said that no one can consign away their basic rights?
But if this is the case, why does torture persist? I don't think Nozick can answer this question. Or at least I think he would perpetually waffle with it. It's hard, in my mind, to think that someone can sign away the basic entitlement to their own humanity (keep in mind that I write this under the basic assumption that we discussed in class, namely, that torture is necessarily the act of dehumanizing someone).
But then what gets me even more is the sense that, under Nozick's theory of justice, the fact that this torture inclusive system is around today proves its justness. That, to me, sounds utterly ridiculous. Living in a world where consent is mandated by physical coercion sounds like justice itself is being tortured...
Sunday, November 15, 2009
In Search of "Truth"
Torture, war, genocide, hatred, mutilation: all of these things have been happening since the beginning of mankind. Hey, weren't Cain and Abel 2nd generation? And already they wanted to kill each other off and take what wasn't theirs? I'm not really super religious, but I'm intrigued also by the idea of religion... but that's a different story. Anyways-- back to the point. Death and murder exist wherever humans are, or so it appears.
So my first question when I'm sitting in class, thinking about human rights and such: If human rights are so inalienable, how come they haven't been respected until modern times? Is this because back in the day, like the Inquisition or the Crusades (I don't know why all my examples are religious, but just try to follow along), humans just couldn't physically understand that all humans might be the same, want the same things, be hurt in the same way? Obviously the learned philosophers were thinking about these things, but does society need to have plentiful leisure time and mass higher-education systems and the internet to get to the point where we can respect the human rights of everyone, including criminals? Are humans innately selfish creatures who see different skin colors as the opportunity to oppress and exploit? As much as I'd love to say that every one of my ancestors had great bones in their body and believed in peace and harmony-- I'm from New Orleans, Memphis, France, England, and who knows where before then. They were slave-holders, cotton-growers, revolutionaries, heretics, and who knows what else. I guess I'm just curious: if we are trying to protect the rights of someone who has killed someone or initiated a genocide, why now? I doubt anyone would have had a problem if we had gotten to Hitler before he got to himself. What makes today so different that suddenly all humans have the right to defend themselves, even if they've made the active effort to extinguish babies or fly planes into the twin towers? I'm not trying to sound pessimistic here (not the way to spell that word I don't think), but I'm really curious why, to me, this seems like a much more recent phenomenon.
Second question: Genocide. What exactly makes genocide "worse" than, say, war of any kind? Is killing the innocent just because of a grudge against their race really worse than starving and murdering millions of Russians? Okay, I used the word "worse" even though I know I shouldn't have... but I'm not trying to say that one is "worse" than something else, I guess I just don't understand how genocide, in particular, is different than any war in history despite the fact that it was purely civilians and purely for the point of extinguishing race.
A last point that I'd like to make is that I have no idea, YET, where I stand on Truth Commissions. (Hopefully I'll figure this out before the paper...) But I find the 4-tiered truth-defining system to be quite intriguing. I think that truth is always objective, and that there are different levels of truth in any and all situations. I think that defining types of truth in specific terms and utilizing a system like that when attempting to get the truth is a step in the right direction, and that the idea of resorative justice is so cool. I'm going to think a little more on this though, and get back to you.
Torture Talk
There are multiple reasons why torture should not or could not be legalized. One reason for this, and possibly the most pertinent, is that studies conclusively show that torture is not an effective means of interrogation. Considering interrogative torture is a major issue within the United States today, it is important that we realize that it is a technique that is not effective.
That being said, torture has caused human beings to give up information in the past. This causes a problem because now there exists a possibility, while small, that torture could cause an individual to share valuable information. For example, let’s imagine that an individual has kidnapped a young girl. Law enforcement apprehends the individual, but he refuses to tell where he is keeping her. Chances are that he will not tell where she is if tortured. But, the possibility remains that if all other interrogation means are exhausted, torture COULD cause him to give up where she is. While I know this might sound simple-minded, I am completely comfortable with using torture in this situation. This being has taken an innocent life into his hands and is willing to let her disappear from the earth, while we refuse to inflict physical pain upon him when the possibility exists that it may work.
I am saying that I am comfortable with torture in this situation, but because of the infinite scenarios and definitions of torture, I see the impossibility of legalizing such and act.
Torture as punishment is another issue that I cannot honestly come to a conclusion on. While the idea of punishment through torture seems like an appealing and useful tool at first in my mind, I do understand and fret over the fact that I do not want a government that disciplines through fear.
But in my mind, there still exists a problem. I understand that the criminals that would be subject to torture as punishment are products of their environment. But every human being is a product of their environment. This does not justify their action! If an individual was abused as a child, an “as a result” murders another human being, where do we stand? Who are we to say that some individuals need physical pain, or at least the possibility of physical pain, as a punishment in order for them to not commit a crime.
Basically, I do not really see a lot of hope. I do not see a society where there are no crimes ever existing. Therefore, there needs to exist some way to correct this problem, and I see no solution that could actually be enacted. The floor is open, if you have any ideas. Eye for an eye, education, torture, the current system, or some brilliant new correctional scheme, you pick.
Justice in the Courtroom
Obviously, based on the principals that establish our government, a trial in the civil courts is the surest way our government can attempt to seek out a bit of justice for the horrible events that happened on September 11th. This certainly seems to be the moral high ground as far as justice by our laws is concerned. However, it is highly unfortunate that this sort of trial will most assuredly become a media circus of never before seen proportions. This point has been raised repeatedly over the weekend news cycle because as many of the pundits have rightly assumed, a huge spectacle is probably just what someone like Khalid Sheikh Mohammed would prefer.
But in light of our classroom discussions I think the most pertinent question to ask is whether or not our civil court system can appropriately work through this trial without making a mockery of the process. Because if a fair trial is set in motion, it will be a dream case for those providing the defense. Since the courthouse is literally blocks away from the place where the World Trade Center once stood, what competent defense attorney wouldn't file for a change of venue? Or better yet have a large portion of the evidence thrown out for a litany of reasons - torture, chain of evidence custody, or improper discovery due to national security issues.
At best we can hope that the trials will be executed with as few disturbances as possible, but I think there is little doubt that a savvy defense attorney could give his or her clients a propaganda tool of very dangerous proportions. But we can look to the trial of Omar Abdel Rahman for some solace. He was the blind sheik that was tried in a civil court for his role in the 1993 World Trade Center bombings. And that trial went forward without making a mockery of the court system. But there is no doubt that the tragedy that brought to U.S. soil on September 11 was much much worse than any other act of terrorism ever conceived. And the subsequent capture and treatment of men like Khalid Sheikh Mohammed will certainly make these upcoming cases arguably some of the most complex judicial proceedings that our court system has ever faced.